3. CONCEPTS ARE THE MASTER-BUILDERS OF THE PERCEPTIBLE WORLD

 

The “inwardly” and “outwardly” extending differentiation builds (in the case of the example that was considered) the tree in its own configuration within its world. What occurs during this construction must however be considered even more precisely.

            As cognitive beings, we do not find such a world that would be ready-made, pre-given. This finished pre-given world, of which one assumes (depending on the evaluation of our cognitive abilities) that in our striving for truth and reality we can either copy or not copy, is a false premise that still widely dominates under the influence of Kant the current scientific paradigm and disposition. Unnoticed but with a tremendous expressive force, it has taken possession of the mentality of the entire civilized world as well as its civilizational vibrancies. It is one of the greatest hindrances to a meditative culture of one’s personal life. Therefore these deliberations, which purport to be an incentive to pursue a modern path of meditation, must deal at least to some extent with this mistake.[1]

            The unbiased introspection of our cognitive behavior shows something else than what the notion of a ready-made pre-given world would want to suggest to us. As cognitive beings we do not, as is usually assumed today, copy a finished world pre-given to us with necessarily insufficient means or even with those means altogether restricted to punctuation. As cognitive beings we rather construct reality (in a subconscious, continually formative web-of-being) from both of its basic components: the incoherent percepts conveyed to us by our senses, and the concepts of our thinking that on the basis of their own nature are coherent. By virtue of their binding ability as well as their ability to adapt to the percepts, they are the tireless master-builders of the perceptible world. They differentiate and integrate the phenomenal richness of the world from a subordinated state of materiality to the fullness of intrinsically subdivided shapes incorporated in a universal structural fabric. It is through our conceptional activity, our thinking will as cognitive beings that we put this structural event to work.

            Reality is, therefore, in so far as we become aware of it in the waking state of mind, our continual structural enactment. Granted, we perform this for the most part subconsciously.  When one (as is done here) understands under cognition to be the unification of percept and concept, then one must therefore distinguish a conscious and an unconscious part of the cognitive process. One becomes thereby aware that our consciousness realm, independent of its degree of wakefulness, is permeated by a formative event of a cognitive nature. Through introspection of our cognitive conduct, we can raise our subconscious structural act retrospectively to fully elucidated consciousness.    

            The consciousness-raising of and the research into this structural enactment of human cognition (that for the human beings of today proceeds initially to a great extent subconsciously), is dealt with in the first main part of The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity [2], that work by Rudolf Steiner that forms the basis of his entire research. In so far as in the framework of these deliberations about the nature and practice of meditation a characteristic of the productivity of human cognition must be given, these deliberations can also be taken as a sketchy introduction into that work. This introduction is in our context indispensable because without insight into the nature of cognition nobody can form appropriate notions about the nature and practice of modern meditation. This will become clear from the following.

                What happens when the conceptual binding components (the means of discrimination or And-metamorphoses as hierarchically structured forms of discernment)  are unified with the disconnected percepts? They are connected – yet on the basis of a process that is only possible because the hereby proceeding change is pre-disposed in the conceptual binding components. The concepts as contents in each case of a general sort are linked to each other according to their own intrinsic context. They are therefore in this form not assigned to individual things.  Each concept embraces rather a whole range of individual examples (of which on their part each one is a structured group of concepts) for which it is qualified. The concept tree embraces in its universality all trees, the concept dog all dogs, the concept bud all buds. Concepts are according to the usage of the Scholastics universals. However, when the general concept tree is connected with the perceptual realm of a certain tree, a certain oak in a correlation enacted in an attentive cognitive fashion, it then loses its universality through this individualized determination. It no longer possesses this mobility with which it can be connected to numerous trees. It has coagulated in the open joints of the as yet unconnected partial percepts and has congealed between them in the solidified state of such a solid bond. This can be recognized by the fact that after the unification of concept and percept, one no longer has a mobile formative element that like a Proteus can assume numerous shapes.  Instead, our morphogenic wealth of forms now also belongs to the shape adapted to the individual case. After the unification process, we can, like a plastic material hardened in a counter die, detach this shape again from its perceptual traps and, independent of its detention, make us conscious of this with the help of its imprint. We become aware of this when without an outer percept we remember the tree with which we have cognitively connected ourselves.[3] We are capable of these remembrances because we can not only form the general fluid concept ”tree”, but also its individualized and hardened form. Our thinking will has not only access to the universal “tree” but also to the representation of a certain tree, the individualized one. The representation is an individualized concept. From the unformed materiality of our percepts has originated through the process of individualization, on the one hand, the structured shape of the tree and from the mobile universal, and on the other hand, a hardened individualie.

            The process of individualization demands an even more detailed examination. This process, as has been shown, is significant for the concept as well as the group of percepts assigned to it. The individualization of the concept corresponds with respect to the percepts to an opposite process. For the latter are universalized. For every percept belonging to a certain tree, a certain oak is a solitary one as long as it is not integrated by the concept in the process of individualization into a structural framework. Through this conceptual act every single percept is spun into the manifold structural fabric of the oak,  making it a part moreover of the multi-membered and multi-related surroundings. Through the individualization of a concept, the particulars apprehended by it are universalized. For from each one of them now run connecting threads to other percepts and through their connections they partake of an expanding relational fabric of an ever more dilating generality. Therein now streams however the previously concealed, now disclosed property manifestation of every perceptual particular on and on.

            The proper evaluation of the morphogenetic process sketched here is impaired above all by two prejudices that have nestled into the current scientific, but also general mode of consciousness. Since they are not only suited to raise doubt concerning the reality content of the foregoing, but also to lead to serious disorders of a modern meditative undertone, it is necessary to briefly deal with them here.

            One of these prejudices concerns the intrinsic nature of the general concepts, the universals. One sees in them, according to a highly influential theory, namely only abstract summaries of uniformities or essentials of the perceptible things. This theory of abstraction therefore does not concede any proper content to the concepts, which is only supposed to appertain to the perceptible things. The so-called general concepts would thus not possess any objective reality, they would merely have a subjective significance as orientational patterns of cognitive human beings. The theory of abstraction fails to recognize the process of becoming aware of reality as characterized in the foregoing. It presupposes this as something ready-made, from which individual components can be abstracted for subjective use. It does not practice the introspection of the unification process of percept and concept, which does not copy reality but brings reality about. It moreover does not observe the distinctness of the basic elements that merge into this unification process. Unprejudiced introspection namely demonstrates that, contrary to this theory of abstraction, contentless patterns of orientation from the supposedly contentful, perceptible available reality is not possible. For the pure concepts are on the basis of their incoherence completely contentless. They can therefore not be the contentual precept of the process of abstraction. The general concepts are therefore the conveyors of content, and generality as such precedes logically and also processually the forming of individualized formative structures. Not generality is posterior but individuality.

            The other prejudice to be considered here is namely determined by the still to this day continuing influence of Kant, even though it has roots with a long history. According to this prejudice, all conceptual means of classification that we have at our disposal are ascribed to the human species. Our general human psychic organism is supposedly natured in such a way that we become aware of the impressions of an outer reality conveyed by our senses in certain structural ways of a conceptional nature, which are characteristic for human perceptive behavior, but which have no similarity with reality as such. All ordering features of the contents of our consciousness would accordingly be of a subjective nature. This hypothesis contains numerous defects, of which only the following are mentioned:

1. It likewise presupposes a reality that for the human process of cognition is ready-made and pre-given, whereas the content of consciousness that exhibits the characteristic of reality, also according to Kant’s construct, originates first within the cognitive process and is afterwards transposed to a hypothetical beyond.

2. This supposed reality beyond our consciousness must be represented within the – as subjectively premised – consciousness realm necessarily without consciousness-like features, thus totally contentless. It is therefore an outwardly transposed element of the cognitive content, namely the totally contentless percept, which is thereby arbitrarily duplicated.

3. The concepts are admittedly grasped through a subjective act of the thinking will, yet present themselves in their logical legality inaccessible to subjective arbitrariness. They are a spiritual realm based on its own foundations that within its order (which Kant fails to notice) assigns to the subjective as well the objective element its proper conceptually befitting place and rank in this supersubjective and superobjective realm.  What is first capable of explaining the nature of human cognition and even the nature of the human being as an instance superior to them, cannot in turn be explained from human nature, which after all cannot be understood out of itself. The conceptual world is such an absolute instance of self-determination from which all other determinations first contingently emerge.

4. The unification of percept and concept cannot be attributed to the activity and nature of our organism.  For in the forming and handling of concepts we suppress the activity of our organism. It is the latter that through our nervous and sensory system conveys us the percepts, to which on the basis of their incoherence must first be directed the constructive structural function of the concepts. The context, which as such pertains to reality and which is driven back by our organism, is therefore returned to the derealized reality by the suppression of our organism. The contextualization is therefore not part of our organism but is contrary to the latter. Now it could indeed be objected that hereby merely one of the systems of our organism suppresses another one, the constitutional-subjective realm would thus not be exceeded. This objection overlooks the self-determination of the world of ideas that is superordinate to all other determinations. The absoluteness of this order, from which all other structures are only derived, is evident from the fact that after the conceptual grasping of the objectively corresponding context we are capable of making predictions and result-oriented preplanning. If our structural means were only of a constitutional-subjective nature, they could not achieve objective successes. Thinking is therefore a superconstitutional structural element that empowers us to grasp a subject and object overlapping reality and thus to harmonize the subjective and objective in a predictable procedure.

            With that, enough may have been said for the present context to refute these disturbing prejudices. What has been put forward here could in a more elaborate cognitive scientific and anthropological context be motivated in much more detail. Especially the significance and activity of our organism within our overall constitution and the total reality would become understandable. From this would in the face of doubt emerge solidly ascertained criteria of discernment about the constitutionally contingent and the constitutionally unspoiled and untouchable.          

 


[1] The author has dealt extensively with this matter elsewhere, e.g. in his works Intuition und Beobachtung, Vol. I and II, Stuttgart 1977 and 1978. Partly translated as Intuition and Observation,  by Sophia Walsh, Spicker Books 1986 (sold-out).

[2] This was the original title suggested by Rudolf Steiner. It was subsequently also translated as Philosophy of Freedom and more recently in Intuitive Thinking As a Spiritual Path: A Philosophy of Freedom, both first mentioned title are used here as seemed appropriate.

[3] The process involved here can in the framework of this essay not be covered in detail. Extensive presentations can be found in the following books by the author Struktuurphänomenologie, Dornach 1983 (“Structural Phenomenology”, not yet translated) and Goethes universalästhetischer Impuls, Dornach 1987 (“Goethe’s Universal Aesthetic Impulse”, not yet translated either.)  

No comments:

Post a Comment

PREFACE BY THE TRANSLATOR

This work was originally published in German as Was ist Meditation? - Eine grundlegende Erörterung zur geisteswissesschaftlichen Bewusstsein...